Connect with us

    Hi, what are you looking for?

    History

    Understanding The Role Of Disability In Ancient Greek Law And Social Structure

    Image Source: PeopleImages.com - Yuri A / Shutterstock
    Collectively, the establishment of public assessments for state assistance, the legal case itself, and our preserved defense oration inevitably prompt inquiries regarding the understanding of “disability” and perspectives toward the disabled within Athenian culture and the broader ancient Greek civilization. Similar to numerous identities, definitions of disability and the identification of who is disabled are socially constructed and historically contextualized (Rose 2003; several essays in Breitweiser 2012; Laes, Goody, and Rose 2013). Contemporary research on disability in the ancient Greek context has contradicted enduring beliefs that individuals with physical and mental disabilities were uniformly marginalized recipients of pity and disdain (e.g., Rose 2003; Sneed 2020; Sneed 2021).
    Those with physical and/or mental challenges were recognizable, integrated, and frequently thriving members of Greek culture. Children with physical disabilities were often affectionately nurtured into adulthood rather than routinely abandoned at birth (Sneed 2021). Ancient healing sanctuaries, often visited by those with physical challenges, were designed with considerations for accessibility (Sneed 2020). The acceptance and assimilation of disabled individuals within society is also mirrored in the lexicon surrounding disability. Despite their abundance, Ancient Greek terminology for disability lacks the systematic medical specificity common in contemporary societies.
    This overall ambiguity has been interpreted as additional evidence for the “entwined status” of disabled individuals within Greek society (Samama 2016: 121). Drawing from this data, disability scholar Martha Rose has recently contended that ancient Greeks did not perceive a category of individuals as “disabled” in a manner comparable to our current classifications, which function within a rigid divide of “able-bodied” and “disabled” (Rose 2003, Rose 2016). Instead, Greeks understood individuals as possessing the potential to shift between diverse physical and mental states that could be categorized as able-bodied or disabled throughout their lives.

    While academics such as Martha Rose have contested the existence of a conceptual category of “the disabled” within the ancient Greek mindset similar to our modern definitions (Rose 2003: 95-100), Lysias 24 offers evidence, corroborated by other references, that Athenians indeed held some awareness of “disabled” men as a safeguarded category of citizens (Dillon 1995; Penrose 2015; Dillon 2016). Two times in the oration (Chs. 4 and 13), Lysias has the accused mention the accuser’s claim that he is not one “of the disabled” (τῶν ἀδυνάτων). It is quite likely that the defendant is paraphrasing or quoting the (now lost) speech of the accuser, and the use of the substantive adjective implies that this term refers to a recognized class or category of citizens.

    Who precisely were these οἱ ἀδυνάτοι and what criteria determined their classification? How does this category of “disabled” (assuming its existence) correspond with and differ from our contemporary classifications? The defendant in Lysias 24 asserts that his accuser claims he is not one “of the disabled” because he receives income from a workshop and rides a horse. Collectively, these two allegations imply that for an (male) citizen to be classified as an οἱ ἀδυνάτοι and thus be eligible for state support, he must live with a physical impairment that hinders his ability to earn an income. The Athenian Constitution (Ath. Pol.), a document attributed to Aristotle or one of his students outlining the history of the Athenian political framework and detailing significant institutions, lends credence to this interpretation. The practice of public examinations (dokimasia), previously mentioned, forms one of the political institutions reviewed by the author of the Athenian Constitution. This dialogue addresses the public evaluation of citizens for who qualifies for state assistance (Ath. Pol. 49.4 and discussion at Rhodes 1981: 570-71):

    The Council evaluates the disabled (τοὺς ἀδυνάτους); for there exists a law which mandates that individuals with less than three minai [of property] and who are physically impaired (τὸ σῶμα πεπηρωμένους) to such an extent that they are unable to work, undergo an assessment before the Council, and that the Council grants them two obols daily, at public cost, for their support.

    Similar to Lysias many years prior, the author of the Athenian Constitution employs ἀδύνατος to describe a community of citizens whose physical disabilities bar them from earning a livelihood, thereby resulting in poverty. Rose (2003: 96) misinterprets Aristotle’s Greek (Dean-Jones 2005: 532) when she asserts that the law broadly categorized οἱ ἀδυνάτοι as any male citizen unable to sustain himself, regardless of physical disability.

    From this evidence, it is reasonable to conclude that Athenian society possessed an understanding of “the disabled” as a protected segment of its citizenry. Concurrently, it is clear that this categorization or identification of “disability” diverges significantly from our modern perceptions in crucial aspects. For in Athenian law (and Athens seems to be the sole Greek city to legislate concerning physical disabilities), a physical disability alone would not render a citizen eligible for state assistance or, ostensibly, classify them as οἱ ἀδυνάτοι.

    If that were the case, our defendant would only need to demonstrate his physical impairment to the Council to prevail against his accuser and obtain state support. Indeed, our defendant does refer to visible aspects of his physical disability, particularly his reliance on two canes (24.12 and 24.14), while also acknowledging that his physical appearance alone is insufficient. Thus, disability is not always overtly apparent in ancient culture (Rose 2016). To put it differently, disability in Athenian law is not exclusively a medicalized condition, defined or delineated by the absence of physical (or mental) capability; instead, disability is characterized by a physical impairment that has severely curtailed one’s social functionality.

    Image Source: PeopleImages.com – Yuri A / Shutterstock

    You May Also Like

    Life

    During a recent segment of her show, “The Martha Stewart Podcast,” acclaimed lifestyle guru Martha Stewart openly discussed her method of gracefully welcoming the...

    Entertainment

    Credit: Envato Elements During a recent live performance, Justin Timberlake shared a bold message regarding reconciliation in the face of ongoing critique about his...

    Entertainment

    Utilizing hair extensions entails following specific guidelines. It’s essential not to be stingy, stay away from artificial alternatives, and stay abreast of current fashions....

    Entertainment

    Credit: Unspalsh Ross and Rachel, Knowing Exactly What to Do as Always! An unexpected incident took place as Jennifer Aniston seemed to have overlooked...